 |
John Worrall, 26 Nov. 2011 |
Last night we went to a 65th birthday party for John Worrall, philosopher of science and guitarist in his band
Critique of Pure Rhythm. For the past 20 or more of these years, Worrall and I have been periodically debating one of the most contested principles in philosophy of science: whether evidence in support of a hypothesis or theory should in some sense be “novel.”
A novel fact for a hypothesis
H may be: (1) one not already known, (2) one not already predicted (or counter-predicted) by available hypotheses, or (3) one not already used in arriving at or constructing
H. The first corresponds to
temporal novelty (Popper), the second, to
theoretical novelty (Popper, Lakatos), the third, to
heuristic or
use-novelty. It is the third, use-novelty (UN), best articulated by John Worrall, that seems to be the most promising at capturing a common intuition against the “double use” of evidence:
If data x have been used to construct a hypothesis
H(x), then x should not be used again as evidence in support of
H(x).
(Note: Writing
H(x) in this way emphasizes that, one way or another, the inferred hypothesis selected or constructed to fit or agree with data x. The particular instantiation can be written as
H(x0).)
The UN requirement, or, as Worrall playfully puts it, the “UN Charter,” is this:
Use-novelty requirement (UN Charter): for data x to support hypothesis
H (or for x to be a good test of
H),
H should not only agree with or “fit” the evidence x, but x itself must not have been used in
H's construction.
The problem has arisen as a general prohibition against data mining, hunting for significance, tuning on the signal, ad hoc hypotheses, and data peeking, and as a preference for predesignated hypotheses and novel predictions.